Karl Marx and the Anarchists Paul Thomas


part of what he meant by it was dictatorship in its Roman sense: an



Yüklə 0,52 Mb.
səhifə30/34
tarix16.08.2018
ölçüsü0,52 Mb.
#63401
1   ...   26   27   28   29   30   31   32   33   34
part of what he meant by it was dictatorship in its Roman sense: an
assumption of power for a limited period for the sake of carrying
through tasks specified in advance. A glance at the Oxford English
Dictionary reveals that the use of the term ‘dictatorship’ to signify
absolute power without even a time limit was only just gaining cur-
rency during Marx’s lifetime, although this is the sense in which Baku-
nin used it.

Yet the dictatorship of the proletariat, whatever its connotations,
should not be regarded as an institutional panacea for what was not a
purely institutional problem. To the anarchist he who says ‘politics’
says ‘the state’; but this is palpably untrue of Marx. The goal of a
Marxist politics is the Hegelian goal that man recognize himself in and
through his own creations, this being (as Hegel had recognized) the
only possible basis for intersubjectivity and thereby for community;
the goal in other words is a political goal, the means to its attainment
political means. Marx’s starting-point is the Hegelian perception that
‘ethical order’ and community are impossible in modern civil society,
to which alien politics alone is appropriate. When individuals live apart
from one another, negotiating mutual use in a condition of what Hegel
had called ‘mere isolated subjectivity’, moral rules and political regu-
lations can appear only as alien, abstract and distant. Yet the solution
to alien politics cannot be no politics, but only politics of a different
kind; it cannot be further depoliticization, but only repoliticization of
the required type. Anarchism is not the solution to alienation but the
maximization of a certain kind of alienation - alienation from the
future prospect of genuine community.


Marx’s starting-point was that of an Hegelian distinction between the
state and civil society, and it is significant that no anarchist perceived
this distinction in anything like the same way. Stirner conflated the two
and thought that the state and society alike would fade away once men
began imperturbably to ignore their existence. Proudhon urged his
readers to undermine and undercut the state but from the standpoint
of the very civil society whose rules, those of political economy, he
accepted as having a timeless validity.’" Bakunin, who like Proudhon
awarded a certain primacy to the state in wildly overestimating the


* Albert Hirschmann has wryly pointed out that ‘the modern political argument
for capitalism that is today associated with such authors as [von] Mises, [von]
Hayek and Milton Friedman was originally put forward by none other than
Proudhon. . . [who] fearful of the enormous power of the state. . . in his later
writings conceived of the idea of opposing to this power a similar “absolutist”,
power-that of private property'.
21




social effects of its abolition (Marx’s words about Proudhon, that ‘he
thinks he is doing something great by arguing from the state to society’,
certainly apply to Bakunin too), also confused the state with civil
society, at least to the extent of urging the simultaneous violent destruc-
tion,
la liquidation sociale,
of both.

Marx, however, was party to none of these confusions. He awarded
no primacy to the state, his break with Hegel having dictated quite
different priorities; he rejected the rules of political economy as having
an inhuman application and a purely provisional validity; and he
regarded the state as illusory only in its capacity as community, not in
its capacity as an agency of the means of violence. This means that the
continuity among Marx’s successive attacks on the anarchists, which
this book has been concerned to trace, can readily enough be demon-
strated. Marx did not simply trot out the same arguments again and
again as the occasion demanded, as though he were merely applying
an invariant formula; different, successive issues demanded different,
successive responses, all of which, taken together, reveal a continuity
of outlook and approach that can tell us much about the continuity
of Marx’s thought as a whole. Marx used the same kind of argument,
which is not easily separated from invective, against Bakunin in the
International, as he had already used earlier in his career in his attacks
on Proudhon and Stirner; throughout them he emerges at his least
appealing and at his most hectoring and heavy-handed.


Anarchism does indeed have the ‘broad back’ that Octave Mirbeau
attributed to it.
22 Stirner, Proudhon and Bakunin each raised different
issues that demanded different successive responses from Marx, re-
sponses which played an important part in the elaboration and evolution
of his thought. Yet anarchism, largely under the aegis of Bakuninism,
became not just a doctrine but also, much more importantly, a move-
ment, and this shift has important implications. The Marx-Bakunin
dispute was unlike Marx’s earlier disagreements with anarchists because
its protagonists were actually agreed upon two basic fundamentals:
revolution as opposed to reform, and collectivism as opposed to indi-
vidualism, be this the truculent egoism of Stirner or the no less truculent
‘social individualism’ of Proudhon. Moreover, the battle for collectivism
- much more than the battle for revolutionism - had largely been won
within the ranks of the International itself, to the evident disarray of
the Proudhonists. Yet all these areas of convergence did nothing to
push Marx and Bakunin any closer together, but instead exacerbated
their remaining differences, which quickly came to seem more irrec-
oncilable than ever. Marx’s earlier disdain for anarchism was exacerbated,
not repressed, by his encounter with Bakuninism. This leads us to a
point of some importance. Merely to counterpose those issues on
which Marx and Bakunin could (for different reasons) come to some
residual agreement - that is, revolutionism and collectivism - to those





that still awaited settlement - the role of the proletariat, of secrecy,
conspiratorialism and violence, of capitalism, of the state, of politics
itself - would be much too schematic an approach. The point is, rather,
that the way in which Marx had confronted the earlier issues, and for
that matter the way in which he had confronted earlier anarchists, led
him to try to bring to bear a similar approach to his dealings with
Bakunin.


Anarchism’s transformation from the status of a doctrine to the
level of a movement took place within and
as part of
Marx’s career as
a revolutionist; yet Marx did not adjust his arguments against anarchism
accordingly. To examine the anti-Bakuninist documents written by
Marx and issued under the imprimatur of the General Council is to be
struck time and time again by their similarity, even in the archness of
their tone, to Marx’s earlier anti-anarchist expostulations. Bakunin
simply reminded Marx of all the nonsense he had already encountered
and (at least to his own satisfaction) put to rest. Marx saw in Bakunin-
ism even at its most expansionist little more than something he was
already familiar with - ‘Proudhonized Stirnerism’ or Proudhonism
warmed over and
mis a la Russe. Such designations tell us nothing
about what is distinctive about Bakuninism, the existence and spread
of which indicates that Bakunin himself was much more than one
more thorn in Marx’s flesh. Besides misjudging Bakuninism’s nature
and expansive potential, Marx failed to recognize that doctrinal im-
patience, heavy-handed irony and withering scorn, which had never
been effective in disposing of Proudhonism, would be counter-productive
if brought to bear in so similar a way against Bakunin in the context
of an organization like the International. Marx’s armoury of abuse
served mainly to reinforce accusations that he was dogmatic and
‘authoritarian’; he became in this way the victim of his own earlier
arguments. Even though these arguments are vital to our understanding
of Marx’s thought and career as a revolutionist, the continuity among
them that may readily enough be traced is not one that worked to
Marx’s advantage - or for that matter to ours.


For we are led once again to Marx’s coup de grace at The Hague in
1872: the climax and upshot of a long series of anti-anarchist argu-
ments and manoeuvres which did so much to ensure that ‘proletarian
internationalism’ would turn into the dogma it need (and should)
never have become, and that future Internationals would be ideologi-
cally monolithic in a way the First International was never originally
intended to be. The doctrinal rigidity of future Internationals is on no
account to be defended. It reinforced tendencies within Marxism we
would all be better off without; it is a sorry story of hidebound in-
flexibility, bureaucratization and the stifling of questioning and initiative
from below. These tendencies have never lacked for defenders - defenders
whose bluff was called in May 1968; lovers of the idea of ‘poetic





justice’, or perhaps of Hegel’s ‘cunning of reason’, will be quick to
point out that Bakunin was more right, so to speak, than he could
possibly have known.


Yet the issues Bakunin addressed go beyond dogmatism, just as they
go beyond their immediate setting. They have to do with whether a
transition to socialism is possible without bourgeois society’s having
already attained an advanced stage of development with high levels of
production and strongly established democratic practices which would
provide a reliable foundation for an extension of human freedom. The
point here is not simply that this question has not yet adequately been
answered, but that it has to it certain dimensions we would all do well
to ponder. On the one hand, if we regard history as an automatic,
causal process and the socialist movement, correspondingly, as a ‘necess-
ary’, determined phenomenon - this is still the received view of Marxism
in some quarters - then the transition to a socialist society will be,
likewise, an inevitable development. If all this is true, then moral
impulses and aims would be of no account and socialist politics could
be represented (as they were by Kautsky, for example) as an ethically
neutral technology based on a science of society. Politics would become
supernumerary, the government of persons the administration of things.
This picture of Marxism is not compelling; my hope is to have shown
that it is also radically incomplete.


There is another dimension to our problem. As Barrington Moore
has (somewhat melodramatically) put it,


The chief basis of radicalism (in modernizing countries) has
been the peasants and the smaller artisans in the towns. . . .the
wellsprings of human freedom lie not where Marx saw them, in
the aspirations of classes about to take power, but perhaps even
more in the dying wail of a class over whom the wave of progress
is about to roll.
23

There is much here that is well-founded, particularly after a hundred
years or so of
chercher le proletariat
among committed Marxists. Yet
even to agree with Moore that the proletariat is the
fata morgana of
Marxism should not blind us to deeper questions: whether we can trace
the lineaments of a free and decent society from the voice-prints and
‘dying wails’ of those who were faced with ‘progress’ - here the record
of the anarchists does not uniformly inspire confidence - and whether
freedom (which Moore does not define) and progress are in fact anti-
thetical. It is because there is at least a strain in Marxism that tells us
they are not antithetical but cognate that I find myself in agreement
with the words of Charles Taylor, that ‘the line from Hegel to Marx
remains in many ways the most clear and intellectually structured
theory of liberation in the modern world’.
24


Notes

Introduction

  1. See Anthony Arblaster, ‘The Relevance of Anarchism’, in The
    Socialist Register,
    ed. Ralph Miliband and John Saville, London,
    Merlin Press, 1971, pp. 157-84.


  2. London, Eyre & Spottiswoode, 1964.

  3. Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1962.

  4. George Woodcock and Ivan Avacumovic, The A narchist Prince: A
    Biography of Peter Kropotkin,
    London, Boardman, 1950.

  5. Daniel and Gabriel Cohn-Bendit, Obsolete Communism: The
    Left-Wing Alternative,
    trans. Arnold Pomerans, Harmondsworth,
    Penguin, 1969.


  6. See Daniel Cohn-Bendit, Le Grand Bazar, Paris, Belford, 1976.

  7. Boston, Beacon Press, 1966.

  8. David Apter, ‘The Old Anarchism and the New’, Government and
    Opposition
    (London School of Economics), vol. v, no. 4, autumn
    1970, pp. 397-8.


  9. Robert M. Nozick, Anarchy, the State, and Utopia, New York,
    Basic Books, 1974, p. xi. Nozick’s index contains the interesting
    entry, ‘Anarchism:
    see State of Nature’.

  10. On this, see Isaiah Berlin, ‘Two Concepts of Liberty’, in Four
    Essays on Liberty,
    Oxford University Press, 1970, pp. 118-72.

  11. Judith N. Shklar, After Utopia, Princeton University Press, 1957,

pp. 8-10.

  1. Ibid.

  2. Gerald Brenan, The Spanish Labyrinth, Cambridge University
    Press, 1972, p. 189.


  3. Quoted in Woodcock and Avacumovic, The Anarchist Prince, p. 12.

  4. On Anarchism and the Real World: William Godwin and Radical
    England’,
    American Political Science Review, vol. lxvi, 1972,

p. 128.

  1. Ibid.

  2. Sheldon S. Wolin, review of David McLellan, Karl Marx: his Life
    and Thought
    (New York, Harper & Row, 1973) in the New York
    Times Book Review,
    13 January 1976, pp. 23-4.

  3. Marx-Engels Werke, Berlin, Dietz vol. xxix, 1966, p. 225.


  1. McLellan, Karl Marx, p. 334.

  2. Wolin, review of McLellan.

1 Hegelian roots

  1. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, trans. with notes by T.M. Knox,
    Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1962, §258, p. 157. Cf. G.W.F. Hegel,
    The Phenomenology of Mind, trans. with an introduction by
    J.B. Bail lie, New York and Evanston, Harper & Row, 1967,


pp. 599-610; and, for discussions, Judith N. Shklar, Freedom
and Independence: A Study of the Political Ideas of Hegel’s
'Phenomenology of Mind’,
Cambridge University Press, 1976,
pp. 173-9, and Charles Taylor,
Hegel, Cambridge University
Press, 1975, pp. 185-8,403-27.


  1. On the usually unremarked links between Montesquieu and
    Hegel, cf. Michael Mosher, ‘The Spirit that Governs Cities:


Modes of Human Association in the Writings of Montesquieu
and Hegel’ (doctoral dissertation, Harvard University,


Cambridge, Mass., 1976), passim. My indebtedness to this
manuscript is considerable.


  1. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, §279A, p. 288.

  2. Georg Lukacs, The Young Hegel: Studies in the Relations
    Between Dialectics and Economics,
    trans. Rodney Livingstone,
    London, Merlin Press, 1975, p. 40. See also J. Glenn Gray,
    Hegel
    and Greek Thought
    (originally published under the title Hegel’s
    Hellenic Ideal),
    New York and Evanston, Harper & Row, 1968,
    passim.

  3. G.W.F. Hegel, Early Theological Writings, trans. T.M. Knox, with
    an introduction by Richard Kroner, Philadelphia, University of
    Pennsylvania Press, 1971, p. 149. Cf. Shlomo Avineri, ‘Hegel’s
    Nationalism’,
    Review of Politics (Notre Dame, Ind.), vol. xxiv,
    no. 4, 1962, pp. 461-84, and in general, Avineri’s
    Hegel's Theory
    of the Modern State,
    Cambridge University Press, especially

ch. Ill (pp. 34-61).

  1. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, §258, p. 156.

  2. Ibid., §184, p. 123. George Armstrong Kelly characterizes the
    state’s relation to the individual, cryptically but sensitively, as
    follows:


The problem of life is purpose, order, fulness-lebendiges
Leben ;
the problem of philosophy is justification through
comprehension - the
Sichwissen des Geistes. Life actualizes;
thought eternalizes; they do this to each other. The state
is the amniotic protection for the exchange. Where the
political community is impotent, fragmented or ‘accidental’
to its role, thought retreats to subjectivity and life is
cleaved into private wish and public act, into ‘chimera’ and
prejudice. (
Idealism, Politics and History: Sources of
Hegelian Thought,
Cambridge University Press, 1969, p.348)


In accordance with this ambitious demarcation of the political,

Eric Weil points out that the purely private world of action and
work, civil society, constitutes ‘un monde qui se fait sans vouloir
se faire’; men need not understand what their actions are perforce
bringing about. The state provides the opportunity and where-
withal for such understanding. (Cf. Eric Weil’s valuable
Hegel
et I'etat,
Paris, Presses Universitaires de France, 1950, p. 46.)

  1. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, §260, p. 161.

  2. Ibid., §75, p. 59; cf. §75A, p. 242; §294, p. 191.

  3. Ibid., §273, p. 178.

  4. J.N. Findlay, Hegel: A Re-examination, New York, Collier, 1962,
    p. 324. Hegel believed to the contrary that individuals quite simply
    ‘do not live as private persons for their ends alone’ (
    Hegel’s
    Philosophy of Right,
    §260, p. 161).

  5. Hegel, The Phenomenology of Mind, pp. 520 ff.; Shklar, Freedom
    and Independence,
    pp. 152-63.

  6. Raymond Plant, ‘Hegel’s Social Theory’, New Left Review
    (London), no. 103, May-June 1977, p. 85.

  7. Shklar, Freedom and Independence, p. 156.

  8. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, §324,pp. 209-10. Cf. Shlomo Avineri,
    ‘The Problem of War in Hegel’s Thought’,
    Journal of the History
    of Ideas
    (Chicago), vol. xxii, no. 4, pp. 463-74; Avineri, Hegel’s
    Theory of the Modern State,
    pp. 194-207; Paul Thomas, ‘Hegel:
    Civil Society and War’,
    Proceedings of the 4th Biennial Meeting

of the American Hegel Society (Villanova University, Philadelphia,
November 1976), Philadelphia, State University of Pennsylvania
Press, 1978.


  1. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, §324A, p. 295.

  2. Albert O. Hirschmann, The Passions and the Interests: Political
    Arguments for Capitalism Before its Triumph,
    Princeton
    University Press, 1977,
    passim; Sheldon S. Wolin, Politics and
    Vision,
    Boston, Little, Brown, 1960, ch. X, pp. 352 ff.; Joseph
    A. Schumpeter, ‘The Sociology of Imperialisms’ (1917) in
    'Imperialism ’and ‘Social Classes’, New York, Kelly, 1951.

  3. Montesquieu, L ’Esprit des lois, X, 7; XX, 2; cf. Hirschmann,

The Passions and the Interests, pp. 71, 80.

  1. John Maynard Keynes, The General Theory of Employment,
    Interest and Money,
    London, Macmillan, 1936, p. 374; cf.
    Hirschmann,
    The Passions and the Interests, p. 134.

  2. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, §324, pp. 209-10.

  3. Ibid., §243, p. 149.

  4. Ibid., §244A, p. 277.

  5. Ibid., §245, p. 150.

  6. Ibid., §246, p. 151.

  7. Karl Marx, Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, trans. Annette
    Jolin, ed. and with an introduction by Joseph O’Malley, Cambridge
    University Press, 1970, p. 81; for the same text,
    Marx-Engels
    Collected Works
    in English, New York and London, International
    Publishers, 1975, vol. iii, p. 80. Henceforward these texts are cited
    as O’Malley and MECW iii respectively.





  1. Heinz Lubasz, ‘Marx’s Initial Problematic: The Problem of
    Poverty’,
    Political Studies (Oxford), vol. xxiv, no. 1, March
    1976, p. 27.


  2. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, §244A, pp. 277-8.

  3. Ibid., §244, p. 150; cf. §195, p. 128.

  4. O’Malley, p. 142;MECW iii, p. 187.

  5. O’Malley, pp. 141-2;MECW iii, p. 186.

  6. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, §65, p. 52.

  7. Ibid., §66, pp. 52-3.

  8. Ibid., §67, p. 54.

  9. Ibid.

  10. Hegel, The Phenomenology of Mind, pp. 228-40. Cf. Alexandre
    Kojeve,
    Introduction a la lecture de Hegel, Paris, NRF, 1947,
    especially pp. 52 ff., for an influential interpretation; and G.A.
    Kelly, ‘Notes on Hegel’s “Lordship and Bondage”’,Review
    of
    Metaphysics
    (Chicago), June 1966, pp. 780-802, for a criticism
    of Kojeve.


  11. Karl Marx, ‘Critique of Hegel’s Dialectic and Philosophy as a
    Whole’, in T.B. Bottomore, ed.,
    Karl Marx: Early Writings, New
    York, McGraw-Hill, 1964, pp. 198-9, 201; MECW iii, pp. 329, 332.


  12. Marx, “Critique”, p. 203; MECW iii, p. 333.

  13. Marx, “Critique”, p. 202; MECW iii, p. 332.

  14. Marx, “Critique”, pp. 213-14; MECW iii, p. 342.

  15. O’Malley, p. 32; MECW iii, p. 31.

  16. O’Malley, p. 81; MECW iii, p. 80.

  17. O’Malley, pp. 77-8; MECW iii, p. 77. Cf. Herbert Marcuse, Reason
    and Revolution: Hegel and the Rise of Social Theory,
    Boston,
    Beacon Press, 1968, p. 208.


  18. O’Malley, p. 22; MECW iii, p. 21.

2 Alien politics

  1. Marx, Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, trans. Annette
    Jolin, ed. and with an introduction by Joseph O’Malley, Cambridge
    University Press, 1970 (henceforward cited as O’Malley), pp. 91,
    64; to be found also in
    Marx-Engels Collected Works (hencefor-
    ward cited as MECW), vol. iii, New York and London, Inter-
    national Publishers, 1975, pp. 91, 63.


  2. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, trans. with notes by T.M. Knox,
    Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1962, §182A, p. 266.


  3. O’Malley, p. 31; MECW iii, p. 30.

  4. Marx to Arnold Ruge, May 1843, in MECW iii, p. 137.

  5. O’Malley, p. lvijcf. pp. 98-101 (MECW iii, pp. 98-100).

  6. O’Malley, p. 111; MECW iii, p. 111.

  7. Marx, ‘On the Jewish Question’, in T.B. Bottomore, ed., Karl
    Marx: Early Writings,
    New York, McGraw-Hill, 1964 (hence-
    forward cited as Bottomore), p. 30; MECW iii, p. 167.


  8. Marx and Engels, The German Ideology, trans. Clemens Dutt,


ed. Salo Ryazanskaya, London, Lawrence & Wishart, 1965,
pp. 91-2;MECW v, p. 78.


9 O’Malley, p. 72;MECW iii, p. 72.

  1. Ibid.

  2. O’Malley, p. 82, cf. p. 106;MECW iii, p. 81, cf. p. 106.

  3. O’Malley, p. 73; MECW iii, p. 73.

  4. O’Malley, p. 32; MECW iii, p. 32.

  5. Ibid.

  6. Bottomore, p. 128; MECW iii, p. 165; O’Malley, p. 32; MECW iii,
    p. 32.


  7. Bottomore, p. 28; MECW iii, p. 165.

  8. Bottomore, p. 31; MECW iii, p. 168.

  9. O’Malley, p. 32; MECW iii, p. 32.

  10. Bottomore, p. 7; MECW iii, p. 149.

  11. Bottomore, pp. 9-10; MECW iii, p. 151.

  12. Bottomore, p. 21 ;MECW iii, p. 159-60.

  13. Marx and Engels, The Holy Family, in MECW iv, p. 117.

  14. The German Ideology, p. 93.

  15. Bottomore, pp. 13-14; MECW iii, pp. 153-4.

  16. Bottomore, p. 26; MECW iii, p. 164.

  17. Bottomore, pp. 24-5; MECW iii, pp. 162-3.

  18. The Holy Family, in MECW iv, pp. 120-1.

  19. Bottomore, p. 31; MECW iii, p. 168.

  20. Marx, The Critique of the Gotha Programme, in Marx-Engels
    Selected Works,
    Moscow, Foreign Languages Publishing House,
    1962 (henceforward cited as MESW), vol. ii, p. 32.


  21. Ibid.

  22. MESWii, p. 33.

  23. Ibid., pp. 33-4.

  24. Marx and Engels, The Manifesto of the Communist Party, in
    MESW i, p. 38.


  25. Ralph Miliband, ‘Marx and the State’, in R. Miliband and John
    Saville, eds,
    The Socialist Register, 1965, New York, Monthly
    Review Press, 1965, p. 280. This pioneering article has now been
    extended: cf. R. Miliband,
    Marxism and Politics, Oxford
    University Press, 1977,
    passim.

  26. The Critique of the Gotha Programme, in MESW ii, p. 32.

  27. Marx, The Poverty of Philosophy: Response to ‘The Philosophy
    of Poverty’ of M. Proudhon,
    New York, International Publishers,
    1963, p. 83.


  28. Ibid., p. 174.

  29. Marx, ‘Critical Marginal Notes on the Article “The King of
    Prussia and Social Reform.” By a Prussian’, in MECW iii, p. 204.


  30. The German Ideology, pp. 357-8; MECW v, pp. 329-30.

  31. Critical Marginal Notes’, in MECW iii, p. 199.

  32. Ibid., p. 197.

  33. Ibid., pp. 197-8.

  34. The German Ideology, p. 78; MECW v, p. 90.

  35. The Manifesto of the Communist Party, in MESW i, pp. 54, 36.




  1. Marx, ‘Die moralisierende Kritik und die kritisierende Moral.
    Beitrag zur deutschen Kulturgeschichte. Gegen Karl Heinzen’.
    Original in
    Marx-Engels Gesamtausgabe, Moscow, 1932 etseq.,
    1/6. Partial translation in H.J. Stenning, ed.,
    Karl Marx: Selected
    Essays,
    New York, International Publishers, 1926; this
    quotation is from Stenning, pp. 136-7.


  2. The Holy Family, in MECW iv, p. 113.

  3. E.P. Thompson, The Making of the English Working Class, New
    York, Vintage, 1966, pp. 9-10.


  4. Marx, The Class Struggles in France, 1848-50, in MESW i, pp. 142
    189-90.


  5. Ibid., p. 189.

  6. Marx, The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, in MESW i
    p. 312.


  7. Marx, Preface to the second edition of The Eighteenth Brumaire,
    in MESW i, p. 244.

  8. The Eighteenth Brumaire, in MESW i, pp. 331-2.

  9. Marx, The Civil War in France, in MESW i, p. 518.

  10. The Eighteenth Brumaire, in MESW i, p. 332.

  11. Ibid., p. 284.

  12. The Civil War in France, in MESW i, p. 518.

  13. The Eighteenth Brumaire, in MESW i, pp. 284-5.

  14. Ibid., pp. 285-6.

  15. Ibid., p. 288.

  16. Ibid., p. 333.

  17. Ibid., p. 333.

  18. Ibid., p. 334.

  19. Ibid., pp. 340-1.

  20. Ibid., pp. 340-1.

  21. The Civil War in France, in MESW i, p. 518.

  22. The Eighteenth Brumaire, in MESW i, p. 342.

  23. Ibid., pp. 343-4.

  24. On the Jewish Question’, in Bottomore, p. 16; MECW iii, p. 356.

  25. The Eighteenth Brumaire, in MESW i,
    Yüklə 0,52 Mb.

    Dostları ilə paylaş:
1   ...   26   27   28   29   30   31   32   33   34




Verilənlər bazası müəlliflik hüququ ilə müdafiə olunur ©www.genderi.org 2024
rəhbərliyinə müraciət

    Ana səhifə