Semantics Why does a sentence mean what it means?



Yüklə 445 b.
tarix16.11.2017
ölçüsü445 b.
#10678



Semantics

  • Why does a sentence mean what it means?

  • What are the meanings of words and how do they come together to make larger meanings (i.e. phrases, sentences)?

  • Perhaps the only level of linguistic description actually needed for there to be language…?



Overview



Machine Translation

  • Can we make a computer program to translate text between languages automatically?



MT: Morphological Analysis

  • Direct word-to-word mapping

  • Billy eats the cake quickly.

  • Billy come la torta rápidamente.

  • (Spanish)



MT: Morphological Analysis

  • Word-to-word mapping doesn’t work well.

  • Billy ate the cake quickly.

  • Billy keki çabukça yedi.

  • (Turkish (I hope))



MT: Morphological Analysis

  • Word-to-word mapping doesn’t work well.

  • What did Billy eat quickly?

  • Billy neyi çabukça yedi?

  • (Turkish (I hope))



MT: Morphological Analysis

  • Word-to-word mapping doesn’t work well.

  • Wawirri kapi-rna panti-rni yalumpu.

  • “Kangaroo will-I spear that.” .

  • I will spear that kangaroo.

  • (Warlpiri, from Hale (1983) via Legate (2002)).



MT: Syntactic Analysis

  • Tree-to-tree mapping:



MT: The Pyramid



MT: Syntactic Analysis

  • Even syntactic MT runs into trouble.

  • Let’s take a brief trip into quantifier scope ambiguity…



Quantifier Scope Ambiguity

  • Two students met with every teacher.

  • (Syntactically unambiguous.)

  • Semantically ambiguous.

    • Two particular students each met all of the teachers.
    • Each teacher was visited by two students, but possibly different students meeting with each.


Quantifier Scope Ambiguity

  • 1 2



Quantifier Scope & MT

  • Unfortunately, not all languages have the same quantifier scope ambiguities.

  • Proper translation requires recognition (& maybe resolution) of ambiguity, and then selection of appropriate form in the target language.



Quantifier Scope & MT

  • English: Everyone loves someone.

    • Ambiguous.
  • Japanese: Daremo-ga dareka-o aisite-iru.

    • everyone-NOM someone-ACC love
    • Unambiguous. “Everyone loves someone or other.”
    • Using this translation would be wrong unless the computer has resolved the ambiguity, i.e. if it knows what the speaker intended.
  • Japanese: Dareka-o daremo-ga aisite-iru.

    • Ambiguous.
    • Close to English “Someone, everyone loves.”
    • A (potentially) awkward translation if the other one would work.
    • (source: Kuno, Takami, and Wu 1999)


MT: Semantic Analysis

  • The holy grail of MT.

  • Obviously a computer cannot truly understand anything, but it has to have a symbolic representation of the meaning.

    • Translate the input sentence into the ‘interlingua’ which represents the full original meaning.
    • Translate ‘interlingua’ into the target language.


Other Practical Applications

  • Question-Answering

  • Automated Summarization

  • Existing solutions don’t use any sophisticated syntax or semantics.

    • Because when they try…


Negative Polarity Items

  • NPIs are words that seem to only be allowed in negative contexts.

    • I did not see anything/any books at the store.
    • I didn’t get paid a red cent for my trouble.
    • I have not ever been to Mexico.
    • I don’t give a damn about the homework.
    • * I saw any book at the store.
    • * I got paid a red cent for my trouble.
    • * I have ever been to Mexico.
    • * I give a damn about the homework.


Negative Polarity Items

  • What constituents a negative context?

    • I didn’t see anyone at the store.
    • I never see anyone at the store.
    • I rarely see anyone at the store.
    • * I saw anyone at the store.
    • * I always see anyone at the store.
    • * I sometimes see anyone at the store.


Negative Polarity Items

  • But there are other licensing contexts too:

    • If I see anyone at the store after hours . . .
    • Students who bought anything from the bookstore . . .
  • What do these have in common?

    • Negation
    • The antecedent of a conditional
    • Relative clauses


Negative Polarity Items

  • This is an upward-entailing context:

  • I saw something in the fishbowl.

  • I saw a fish in the fishbowl.

  • I saw a goldfish in the fishbowl.



Negative Polarity Items

  • This is a downward-entailing context:

  • I didn’t see a thing in the fishbowl.

  • I didn’t see a fish in the fishbowl.

  • I didn’t see a goldfish in the fishbowl.



Negative Polarity Items

  • If I find a fish in the fishbowl, I will feed it.

  • Is fish in an upward-entailing or downward-entailing context?



Negative Polarity Items

  • If I find a fish in the fishbowl, I will feed it.

  • Situation Feed it?

  • I found a worm (an animal). NO

  • I found a goldfish. YES

  • So the conditional above entails:

    • If I find a goldfish in the fishbowl, I will feed it
  • Goldfish is more specific.

  • It is downward entailing.



Negative Polarity Items

  • Students who bought a book will get a rebate.

  • Situation Rebate?

  • I bought merchandise. NO

  • I bought a textbook. YES

  • This is also downward-entailing.



Negative Polarity Items

  • If Clinton wins in ’08, some politicians will be happy.

  • Clinton wins. Let’s see who is happy.

  • Group Happy?

  • some people YES

  • Republicans NO

  • This is upward entailing.

  • The antecedent of a conditional is downward-entailing, but the consequent is upward-entailing.



Negative Polarity Items

  • Licit only in downward-entailing contexts.

    • Where replacement with a more specific term yields a sentence entailed by the original.
  • NPIs also have a syntactic requirement.

    • “c-command” under the standard generative model of sentence structure
  • There are also positive-polarity items.



Object vs. Meta Language

  • When describing meaning, it doesn’t help to use the words we’re trying to define.

  • The quick brown fox jumped.

    • What does this mean?
    • It doesn’t help to just repeat the sentence.
    • We need a controlled vocabulary that we can agree on to describe language.


Object vs. Meta Language

  • I will use italics for utterances of English, our object language.

    • The quick brown fox jumped.
  • I will use CAPITALS for the meta-language, the language to talk about language.



Object vs. Meta Language

  • deep blue oceans

  • What does this mean? I think it means things that are…

    • OCEANS
    • AND DEEP
    • AND BLUE
  • Reduction of meaning into smaller pieces:

    • AND , OCEANS , DEEP , BLUE


Object vs. Meta Language

  • We can’t possibly list the meaning of every phrase. (Is there a longest phrase?)

  • But we can list the meaning of every word.

    • “oceans” “deep” “blue”
  • And we can add a little bit of glue and some rules for putting the meanings together.



Object vs. Meta Language

  • deep blue oceans

  • ADJ ADJ …. N

  • The meaning 〚…〛 of a noun phrase of the form above is the conjunction of the meaning of its parts.

    • 〚ADJ1 ADJ2 ADJ3 . . . N〛 = things that are〚ADJ1〛 AND〚ADJ2〛AND 〚ADJ3〛AND〚N〛


Compositionality

  • The meaning of a constituent is determined by

    • The meaning of its parts
    • The way the parts are put together
    • (And nothing else.)
  • It seems obvious, but there are some complications.



Compositionality Complications: Idioms

  • Idioms

    • Phrases that defy compositionality
    • Meaning of the whole must be listed lexically
  • a red cent (‘nothing’)

  • give a damn (‘care’)

  • kick the bucket (‘die’)

  • sleeping with the fishes (‘killed’)

  • the cat has got your tongue (‘speechless’)



Compositionality Complications: Idioms

  • Are they just multi-word words?

  • Idioms differ in their rigidity...



Compositionality Complications: Idioms

  • In most idioms, one cannot replace any words and retain the idiomatic meaning:

    • a red cent / *penny / *coin
    • *punch/*tap the bucket
  • But some have replaceable parts:

    • the cat got my/your/the teacher’s tongue


Compositionality Complications: Idioms

  • Some but not all idioms can be syntactically shuffled around (here, passivized):

    • Keep tabs on Henry. (‘track his whereabouts’)
    • Tabs were kept on Henry for three days.
    • Don’t spill the beans. (‘don’t give up the secret’)
    • The beans were spilled already.
    • * The bucket was kicked by the old man.
    • * His tongue has been gotten by the cat.


Compositionality Complications: Idioms

  • This suggests idioms have internal syntactic structure, but perhaps no internal semantic structure.



Compositionality Complications: Idioms

  • This suggests idioms have internal syntactic structure, but perhaps no internal semantic structure.



Compositionality Complications: Non-Intersective Adjectives

  • We previously saw ‘intersective’ adjectives:

    • A hungry alligator is something that is both hungry and an alligator.
    • Something that is a hungry alligator comes from the intersection of the set of hungry things and the set of alligators.
    • 〚ADJ N〛= 〚ADJ〛∩ 〚N〛


Compositionality Complications: Non-Intersective Adjectives

  • There are also non-intersective adjectives:

    • a good plumber is not someone who is both good (in general) and a plumber. He only has to be good at plumbing.
    • a proud father is not necessarily a proud person
    • 〚ADJ N〛= 〚ADJ〛∩ 〚N〛
    • At least a good plumber is a plumber and a proud father is a father. These are called ‘subsective’ because it still finds a subset.
      • 〚ADJ N〛⊆ 〚N〛


Compositionality Complications: Non-Intersective Adjectives

  • Then there are non-intersective, non-subsective adjectives:

    • a former student is not even a student (let alone ‘former’, cf. ‘blue’)
      • The whale is blue.
      • *John is former.
    • an alleged criminal is not (by necessity) a criminal.
    • counterfeit money is not money (arguably, but certainly not the way we usually use money).


Compositionality Complications: Non-Intersective Adjectives

  • How to reconcile non-intersective adjectives with compositionality?

  • If 〚former student〛≠ 〚former〛∩ 〚student〛 then we have to give up either:

    • Compositionality
    • Intersection ∩


Brief Interlude: Functions



Brief Interlude: Functions



Brief Interlude: Functions

  • Notation:

    • SQRT(100) = 10
    • FORMER(〚student〛) = 〚former student〛 =〚former〛(〚student〛)


Compositionality Complications: Non-Intersective Adjectives

  • By treating the meaning of former as a function from one notion to another, we can have a compositional account of former X.

  • For non-intersective adjectives:

    • 〚ADJ N〛= 〚ADJ〛(〚N〛)
    • Treat the meaning of ADJ as a function and apply it to the meaning of N.


Compositionality

  • Meanings can be compositional in two ways:

    • By conjunction/intersection: 〚X Y〛= things that are both〚X〛and〚Y〛 〚X Y〛= 〚X〛∩〚Y〛
    • By function-application: 〚X Y〛= 〚X〛(〚Y〛)


Presupposition

  • A man sat in the witness chair awaiting the next question from the attorney….

  • When did you stop beating your wife?

  • The jury gasps, but the man is simply confused. He responds:

  • But I never beat my wife!



Presupposition

  • The King of France is bald.

  • Huh?

  • It’s not false, per se. It’s just weird.



Presupposition

  • Compare:

  • I don’t think that the Earth is flat.

  • (a true statement)

  • I don’t know that the Earth is flat.

  • (presupposition failure)



Presupposition

  • If an utterance has a presupposition π, then π must be true in order for the utterance to be ‘OK’.

  • Further, π must be established as common ground in the discourse.

  • (Unless the presupposition is ‘accommodated’.)



Presupposition

  • The hallmark of presupposition is that it remains despite negation.

  • Thus we can separate an utterance into two parts:

    • the assertion, which is affected by negation
    • the presupposition, which is not


Presuppositions Under Negation

  • I think the Earth is flat.

    • Assertion: I believe the Earth is flat.
    • Presupposition: None
    • Sentence is false (i.e. a lie), but otherwise OK.
  • I know the Earth is flat.

    • Assertion: I believe the Earth is flat.
    • Presupposition: The Earth is flat.
    • Presupposition is not true, therefore sentence is weird.


Presuppositions Under Negation

  • I didn’t think the Earth is flat.

    • Assertion: I didn’t believe the Earth is flat.
    • Presupposition: None
    • Sentence is true.
  • I didn’t know the Earth is flat.

    • Assertion: I didn’t believe the Earth is flat.
    • Presupposition: The Earth is flat.
    • Presupposition is still not true, therefore sentence is still weird.


Presupposition Triggers

  • definite descriptions (‘the King of France’)

    • π = ‘there is a King of France’
  • quantificational NPs (‘every cat I own’)

    • π = ‘I own at least one cat’
  • factive verbs (‘regret’, ‘know’, ‘discover’)

    • π = the proposition regretted/known/discovered
  • aspectual verbs/adverbs (‘stop’, ‘still’)

    • π = the action was happening previously
  • questions (‘who stole the cookies?’)

    • π = ‘someone stole the cookies’


Presupposition Projection

  • Presuppositions can ‘project’ or percolate up recursively embedded sentences.

  • I think [John knows [the Earth is flat.]]

  • If [John knows the Earth is flat] then . . .

  • Even though ‘think’/‘if’ are not a p-triggers, ‘know’ is, and its presupposition passes through ‘think’/‘if’.



Presupposition Filters

  • On the other hand, presuppositions can be blocked.

  • If the Earth is flat, then a good scientist probably would know the Earth is flat.

  • There is no presupposition here.

  • If π, a presupposition of the consequent, is asserted in the antecedent, it is not a presupposition of the whole sentence.



Presupposition Filters

  • If France had a King, the King of France would be a very powerful man.



Presupposition Accommodation

  • Usually presuppositions have to be established:

    • A man off the street walks up to you and says:
    • I regret that I didn’t buy the tomato.
  • You say: “Oh. You were going to buy a tomato?”

  • The presupposition was not a part of the common ground.



Presupposition Accommodation

  • But sometimes we accept sentences with presuppositions not already established:

  • If the North Korean ambassador turned up, then it is amazing that both the North and South Korean ambassadors are here.

  • (Beaver 2002)

  • π = the S.K. ambassador is here

  • π is ‘accommodated’



Formal Semantics

  • Not just what things mean,

  • but representing meaning & composition in precise logical terms

  • Hashing out the meta language.



Propositional Logic

  • Mathematical representation of meaning.

  • Symbols like p, q stand in for propositions about what is true in the world. Propositions can be either true or false.

  • Let p = ‘It is raining.’

  • p is true iif it is raining.

    • If p is true, it must be raining.
    • If it is raining, p must be true.


Propositional Logic: Connectives

  • Propositions can be combined into formulas using special connectives:

    • and: ∧
    • or: ∨
    • not: ¬
    • if: → (aka implies, conditional)
    • iif: ↔ (aka if and only if, biconditional)


Propositional Logic: Connectives

  • Let p = ‘It is raining.’

  • Let q = ‘It is snowing.’

  • Let r = ‘I will play outside.’

  • (p ∨ q) → ¬ r

  • ‘If it is raining or snowing, then I will not play outside.’



Predicate Logic

  • Predicate logic adds names and predicates on top of propositional logic.

    • KNOWS(JOHN, MARY)
  • Let KNOWS be the predicate that is true just when the first argument knows the second argument.



Predicate Logic: Examples

  • If John meets Mary, then he will know her.

  • MEETS(JOHN, MARY) → KNOWS(JOHN, MARY)



Predicate Logic: Examples

  • On days without a cloud in the sky,

  • whenever my dog Sparky barks, and only when he barks, I take him for a walk.

  • ¬CLOUDY → [BARKS(SPARKY) ↔ WALK(ME, SPARKY)]



Predicate Logic & Natl. Language

  • 〚John〛= JOHN

  • 〚Mary〛= MARY

  • 〚knows〛= KNOWS( … , … )

  • 〚John knows Mary〛= some combination of 〚John〛〚Mary〛and 〚knows〛with either conjunction/intersection or function application



Predicate Logic & Compositionality

  • Formal semantics starts where generative syntax ends.



Predicate Logic & Compositionality

  • Syntax Semantics

  • S → NP1 V NP2 〚S〛=〚V〛(〚NP1〛,〚NP2〛)

  • S → John knows Mary 〚S〛=〚knows〛(〚John〛,〚Mary〛)

  • S → John knows Mary 〚S〛= KNOWS(JOHN, MARY)



Predicate Logic & Compositionality

  • Syntax Semantics

  • CP → if S1 then S2 〚CP〛=〚S1〛 → 〚S2〛

  • (roughly)



Yüklə 445 b.

Dostları ilə paylaş:




Verilənlər bazası müəlliflik hüququ ilə müdafiə olunur ©www.genderi.org 2024
rəhbərliyinə müraciət

    Ana səhifə